DAVID CONAN WOLFSDORF

HOME RESEARCH TEACHING CV PERSONAL CONTACT
  OVERVIEW    
  WORKS    
 

I came up into philosophy through classics and so up into ancient philosophy. Along this path I brought a deep interest in language and philology as well as in philosophical methodology. These have remained abiding concerns.

I cut my teeth on Plato, first on the early dialogues, then working through the remainder of the corpus. My publications on Plato have principally engaged topics in epistemology, logic, metaphysics, ethics, and philosophical psychology.

Presently I am well versed in the ancient tradition from the Presocratics through Plato, Aristotle, Epicurus, and the Old Stoics. My interest in Late Antiquity is largely limited to the light it casts on earlier periods. (My second book Pleasure in Ancient Greek Philosophy and recent papers in ancient philosophy attest to this range and these interests.)

As I gained mastery in the field of ancient philosophy, I began to devote myself more intensively to non-historical areas of philosophy. Following up on my philological background, I turned to the philosophy of language. Along with my interests in ethics and philosophical psychology, this work immediately led me into the metaethical debates between cognitivist and non-cognitivist interpretations of evaluative and normative language. In pursuing this subject, I was increasingly drawn to the resources of contemporary linguistics, mainly formal semantics, but also pragmatic and syntactic theory. The results of this research have, I believe, yielded clearer and sounder foundations for aspects of value theory.

 

For details scroll down or click on these links:

2013-PRESENT

2007-2013

1998-2007

 

   
  2013-PRESENT    
 

My two main current research projects reflect my background in ancient philosophy and my present interest in linguistics and philosophy of language respectively. The former is a collection of essays I have commissioned and am editing entitled Early Greek Ethics. In the last twenty years and especially very recently, a lot of disparate scholarship has been done on Greek ethical philosophical thought and writing from the fifth century BCE to about the first third of the fourth-century BCE, in particular ethical philosophical thought and writing not authored by Plato. The ancient contributors include other associates of Socrates such as Antisthenes, Aristippus, and Xenophon; figures from outside the Socratic circle such as Democritus, Gorgias, Antiphon, and Archytas; and anonymous texts such as the Dissoi Logoi and Anonymus Iamblichi. Generally speaking, in assembling this work I am attempting to define the landscape of early Greek philosophical ethics and in doing that to advance it as a distinctive field of study.

The website for Early Greek Ethics is available here be.

Two of my chapters for the volume, "The Ethics of the Historical Socrates" and "Remarks on the Unity of the Dissoi Logoi" are available on the WORKS page.

The second project is concerned with the foundations of value theory. Its governing question is: What is goodness? I am pursuing this metaphysical question by means of the semantic questions: What do the adjective "good" and the deadjectival nominalization "goodness" mean? In virtue of the distinctive semantic properties of the adjective "good" and the nominalization "goodness," pursuit of the semantic questions has led to a focus on the following linguistic topics: ambiguity, gradability, multidimensionality, context sensitivity, mass nouns, and bare noun phrases. In a nutshell, I argue that "good" is three ways ambiguous. Two of three senses of "good" are gradable. Both of the gradable senses of "good" are multidimensional, i.e. they can be associated with various gradable properties (= dimensions) in various contexts of use. I argue that this aspect (there are others) of the context sensitivity of "good" owes to the fact that "good" denotes a binary predicate, one of whose arguments may be implicit. In contrast to "good," the nominalization "goodness" is not ambiguous. It derives from only one of the three senses of "good." "Goodness" is a mass noun; its denotation is therefore representable as a join semilattice. But owing to the fact that the adjective from which it is derived is gradable, the denotation of "goodness" has additional scalar structure. Finally, it is well known that mass nouns can occur bare, i.e. in argument positions without determiners, and that such occurrences are up to four ways ambiguous. I aim to explain this ambiguity, but haven't yet settled on a satisfying account.

The chapters on ambiguity (in draft) is available on the WORKS page.

 

BACK TO TOP

 
  2007-2013    
 

Around the time that most of the research and writing of Trials of Reason: Plato and the Crafting of Philosophy had been completed I turned my principal attention to the subject of pleasure. My motivations were manifold but primarily two. First I wanted to shift focus from an author or figure or school to a topic or theme. Second I found in the topic of pleasure a nexus of two growing interests: in ethics, especially metaethics, and in philosophy of mind or philosophical psychology. In 2012 I completed Pleasure in Ancient Philosophy (CUP), which examines pleasure in ancient philosophy from pre-Platonic figures through Plato, Aristotle, Epicureans, Cyrenaics, to the Old Stoics. The study also includes some Roman and Late Antique authors who contribute to and discuss the work of these earlier schools and figures. The book examines two basic questions, which I call the identity and kinds questions: What is pleasure? And what kinds of pleasure are there? I hope to have made a strong case that the various ways these figures and schools answer these questions are dialogically continuous. For example, Aristotle’s formulations involve criticisms of Plato, and Epicurus develops Aristotelian contributions. In the penultimate chapter I discuss treatments of the identity and kinds questions in contemporary Anglophone philosophy, precisely from Ryle’s contributions in the late 40s and 50s up to the present. In the final chapter I discuss the relations between the ancient and contemporary treatments. One fundamental, remarkable conclusion of this comparison is that ancient treatments tend to focus on what I call the objects of pleasure, whereas contemporary treatments focus on the attitude toward such objects. I explain this distinction in view of the distinct contexts in which ancient and contemporary treatments of the identity and kinds questions have occurred, namely, within ethics and philosophy of mind respectively.

Here is an interview, for a lay audience, in which I discuss the book be.

BACK TO TOP

 
pagp pic
  1998-2007    
 

The first stage of my professional career focused on Plato’s thought. In line with my historical background my principal interest was understanding Plato on his own terms. My articles on Plato up to about 2008 represent attempts to achieve the objective. They focus on a wide range of Plato’s thought, his ethics, methodology, epistemology, metaphysics, and psychology, as well as on the problem of interpreting any aspect of Plato’s thought given the distinctive challenge and complication of the dialogic form of his writings. Trials of Reason: Plato and the Crafting of Philosophy (OUP 2008) culminated this vein of research. The book pursues two questions: What is Plato’s conception of philosophy? And how is the dialogue form employed in Plato’s presentation of this conception? In brief, I maintain that Plato conceives of philosophy as a kind of motivation, specifically a desire for wisdom, which he conceives as ethical knowledge. The book is then organized as a discussion of Plato’s conception of desire, ethical knowledge, the means of pursuing such knowledge, including the so-called elenctic and hypothetical methods, and the aporetic conclusions in which these pursuits inevitably end. In his early dialogues, Plato introduces philosophy (as he conceives it) and in doing so contrasts philosophy with what I call “counter-philosophical” approaches to life. This contrast serves to explain the dialogic character of Plato’s work. As I put it in the book: Plato’s dramatizations “are not wholly situated within the sphere of philosophical discourse. Rather, one of the basic functions of the texts is to craft philosophy. As the dialogues unfold, philosophical discourse emerges out of the various discourses of the polis. In the process, Plato works to establish why philosophical discourse must be the authoritative political discourse.” As such, I suggest, Plato’s dialogues are as much works of meta-philosophy as philosophy. In short my deepest concern in this early work might be expressed in this way: I was interested in the idea that philosophy is a cultural-historical kind, and I wanted to examine one of its earliest and most important forms. I wanted to understand philosophy by examining one of the seminal ways in which it came into being. My approach to the topic was therefore inextricably historical and philosophical.

BACK TO TOP

  torpic